On Friday, as the major networks called the presidential race for Joe Biden, cheering erupted in the streets of my hometown, Rosendale, NY, as it did in many towns and cities across the country. Joy, mitigated with relief, characterized most responses as people realized the election was over.
But a not uncommon additional sentiment was exhaustion. For most Americans, the last four years consisted of a daily barrage of norm violations, lies, self-dealing, administrative abuses, and illegalities compounded by denial in the face of one of the most serious health threats to face the world since the early part of the twentieth century (and I leave aside a host of other outrages like the ever-present presidential tweets and commentary which served as a sort of droning background noise for the entire four years).
As one woman I spoke with briefly on the street put it: “Thank goodness it’s over; I can go back to thinking about my life!” I imagine this is not at all an uncommon sentiment. After all, we, collectively, have devoted an extraordinary amount of time in the last four years to the public drama emanating out of the White House. I’ve followed politics in the United States closely since I was a teenager, but I can’t remember spending quite so much time doing so as I have during the Trump Presidency.
So on the one hand, the exhaustion seems understandable, as does the desire to concentrate on non-political issues and concerns. But it also reflects a deeper underlying gravitational pull away from the public sphere that characterizes liberalism, and poses a distinct danger to the American democratic project.
The basic premise of liberalism – built into the Latin roots of the word – promises liberty: it’s the desire to maximize space within which we can act without interference, consistent with allowing similar space for others. Political theorists usually refer to this way of thinking about liberty as “negative,” as in Thomas Hobbes’ infamous definition of it as an “absence of external impediment.” Early liberals saw impediments or interference in the demands of government, though – following John Stuart Mill – we can think of public opinion, mores, and norms as other forms of interference, even though they may lack the force of law.
For liberals, human beings need this sort of space to pursue their particular conception of the good life. The government should not tell us what to think, believe, or pursue as an end, so long as we’re not harming others in that pursuit. As rational creatures, we can determine (or not) our own goals and ends, and the state remains as neutral as possible on the question of the good life.
But this reveals a strange apolitical nature at the heart of the underwriting political theory of liberal democracy because the centripetal pull of individual conceptions of the good life pull us away from public concerns into our own private worlds. Success in and focus on the private sphere eclipses our view of the public sphere and makes possible the valorization of the private life.
This is not, of course, to argue that we don’t need some sort of private existence. The household, the family, leisure time, all provide us with welcome relief from the harsh light of the public sphere. But it is to argue that a political theory which points away from the public sphere so definitively run the risk of neglecting to adequately patrol the public sphere.
I suppose what I want to argue is that at its roots, liberalism is a political theory which holds out the possibility of ignoring the public sphere. With adequate constitutional constraints, the government should function like a clock, requiring only the periodic adjustment of an election. I hear versions of this in the relief people express at the election of Biden. Once Biden takes office, we can relax and tend to other affairs.
The truth, unfortunately, is not so simple. Maintaining negative freedom requires not only the lack of external impediment, but also taking the time to ensure that no such impediments will be erected. And this orients the citizen always back toward the public sphere. We cannot resolve political problems definitively. They require, rather, constant monitoring, negotiation, and intervention, and not just by our elected representatives.